AustLII Home | Databases | WorldLII | Search | Feedback

University of Technology Sydney Law Research Series

You are here:  AustLII >> Databases >> University of Technology Sydney Law Research Series >> 2012 >> [2012] UTSLRS 21

Database Search | Name Search | Recent Articles | Noteup | LawCite | Author Info | Download | Help

van Rijswijk, Honni; Anthony, Thalia --- "Can the Common Law Adjudicate Historical Suffering" [2012] UTSLRS 21; (2012) 36 Melbourne University Law Review 618

Last Updated: 10 April 2017

Can Common Law Adjudicate Historical Suffering? Evaluating South Australia v Lampard-Trevorrow (2010)
Honni van Rijswijk and Thalia Anthony

I INTRODUCTION
The case of South Australia v Lampard-Trevorrow[1] opens up key questions about the capacity and willingness of the common law to adjudicate past acts of the state. In Lampard-Trevorrow, the South Australian Court of Appeal dismissed the State’s appeal against the decision of Gray J in Trevorrow v South Australia (No 5),[2] which awarded Bruce Trevorrow damages against the government for his removal from his family as an infant, making him the first member of the Stolen Generations to successfully claim.[3] This article considers the significance of the appeal decision, following the successful trial judgment, by examining what distinguishes the case from past, unsuccessful claims, and its implications for future claimants from the Stolen Generations. In addition, we consider what the case means in terms of the law’s acceptance of a different kind of historical and evidential interpretation from previous cases and how this is channelled into the issue of consent. We argue that the role and interpretation of consent have broad ramifications for law’s potential to adjudicate responsibility for historical harms.
There has been significant criticism of the ways in which courts have interpreted the operation of state power in relation to the Stolen Generations, essentially distancing specific acts of state actors from the context of Stolen Generations policy.[4] This practice has arisen in a number of ways in the cases, through the courts’ evaluation of both legal and factual issues. Trevorrow and Lampard-Trevorrow (hereafter ‘the Trevorrow Cases’) signify a break in the law’s seeming incapacity to adjudicate historical suffering. This break raises the compelling question of whether the common law has now become a site available for the redress of historical injuries suffered by members of the Stolen Generations. How exceptional are the Trevorrow Cases? To what degree does Lampard-Trevorrow open up hope for a new class of claimants? Is the common law now a significant site for the adjudication of these important, enduring harms? Here we explore the implications of the case for law’s role in the future adjudication of historical harms. We argue that Lampard-Trevorrow both opens doors for claimants, based on its broad reading of the legislation and the notion of consent, and closes them, given its specific facts, legislative framework and unwillingness of the court to find false imprisonment or a breach of fiduciary duty arising from the facts.
The purpose of this article is to explore the Trevorrow Cases and offer some insight into the implications for the common law’s potential to adjudicate historical injuries. The article is divided into four substantive parts. Following the introduction, Part II provides the context for the Trevorrow Cases, including a summary of past cases, a description of the different statutory frameworks that were in issue in these cases, and consideration of the impact of these specificities on the outcome in the Trevorrow Cases. Part III provides a critical commentary on the Lampard-Trevorrow Appeal, including the ways it limits some of the trial judgment’s potential. Here, we consider the key findings of the Appeal regarding: liability for negligence and misfeasance in public office; the duty to accord procedural fairness; the discretion to grant an extension of time; and the tort of false imprisonment and breach of fiduciary duty, in respect of which the trial judge’s findings were ultimately overturned, findings which, we argue, limit the potential of Lampard-Trevorrow. In particular, we examine, and lament, the appellate court’s more limited reading of false imprisonment in contrast to the trial judgment. We argue that this cause of action is, first, a more fitting analogy for claims that arise out of the circumstances of the Stolen Generations, in comparison to other categories, and, second, a category that would allow the law to adjudicate a wider range of claims (and so allow the law a greater role in the adjudication of responsibility for historical injuries), since the evidentiary requirements that make these claims so difficult for claimants in this area are reversed in the case of false imprisonment. We also critique the failure of the Court of Appeal to find that the removal led to a fiduciary duty on the part of the state, due to an overly strict interpretation of the scope of fiduciary duties. Part IV examines what we consider to be the key interventions of Trevorrow Cases in the history of the common law’s adjudication of claims relating to the Stolen Generations—namely, the court’s demonstration of a willingness to examine evidence critically and contextually, as well as its critical examination of standards in operation at the time the policies were administered (and willingness to decide questions of responsibility regarding past acts of the state). Both these practices of interpretation signify a break from previous litigation in this area, and augur some potential for the common law’s role into the future. Finally, Part V examines what we consider to be one of the main limitations of the adjudication of these historical injuries at common law, namely the presence of problematic ‘myths’ concerning parental consent, which determine not only the nature of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ litigants, but which also reinforce false and harmful narratives about the operation of power. As a result of Stolen Generations policy, and the courts’ interpretation of the statutory regimes in which this took place, consent has become one of the ‘stories that had normalized state intervention yet at the same time ignored the subjectivity and experience of Indigenous people altogether’.[5]
We conclude that there may be some capacity for the common law to redress historical harms, especially if courts in the future adopt the practices of interpretation from the Trevorrow Cases regarding the significance of past policy and evidence. However, this potential needs to be balanced against the weight of precedent, including the law’s habit in past cases of distancing itself from the role of adjudicating historical wrongs of the state. In some ways, the question is, ‘Will the common law evaluate historical suffering?’ But it is also a question of the possibilities that have been determined by existing precedent. These points naturally raise the normative question of whether the law should become a site for the adjudication of historical and cultural injuries – the injuries of colonisation. A number of people have commented on this question, concluding that litigation is ‘a poor forum for judging the big picture of history’.[6] The Report of the National Inquiry into the Separation of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Children from Their Families, Bringing Them Home, recommended that a reparations scheme be adopted to deal with compensation arising from harms suffered by the Stolen Generations.[7] The advantage of the reparations approach is that it could respond not only by providing compensation that avoids the limitations and vagaries of litigation, thus administering a fairer form of redress, and saving survivors from unnecessary further trauma, but it could also include apologies and acknowledgements, and guarantees that such policies will never be repeated[8]—discursive responses that matter. Such a solution could also redress the problematic myths and narratives that are part of common law history regarding the Stolen Generations cases, including the narrative concerning parental consent. This would provide the opportunity for a freer narrative response to the harms—providing for compensation in conjunction with statements that acknowledge the harms of history, the historical and contemporary complicity of law and society, and compensation without reliance on the problematic myths that are still part of common law adjudication.


PART II THE CONTEXT OF LAMPARD-TREVORROW IN RELATION TO PREVIOUS STOLEN GENERATIONS LITIGATION
In many ways, Gray J’s judgment in Trevorrow, and the appeal that followed it, signify a ‘markedly different ... approach and outcome to what came before it’.[9] At the same time, commentators have pointed to the distinctive nature of the factual and legal basis of the decision, including that it was based on an ‘ideal plaintiff’, and suggested that this may limit its potential.[10] In this section, we briefly summarise the facts of the case, as compared to earlier Stolen Generations litigation, as well as the relevant statutory frameworks courts considered in each case. The motivating question of this section is to what extent the factual circumstances and statutory framework of Trevorrow is exceptional? To what extent is the favourable outcome due to these specificities, or changes in the common law’s approach questions of law, fact and policy, to questions of responsibility for past actions, and acts of the state? And of particular pertinence to our organising question, what does this mean for the future capacity of the common law to redress these historical injuries?
In Kruger v The Commonwealth,[11] nine Aboriginal claimants argued the constitutional invalidity of the Northern Territory’s Aboriginal Ordinance 1918, which purportedly authorised the removal of Aboriginal and ‘half-cast’ children, and that this cause of action gave rise to damages for breach of express and implied constitutional rights.[12] The High Court held that the Ordinance: did not contravene s 116 of the Constitution (freedom of religion);[13] was valid under s 122 of the Constitution,[14] and did not breach any implied right to freedom of movement and association[15] or equality.[16] The High Court rejected claims that the Ordinance was enacted for the purposes of genocide, finding instead that it was ‘beneficial’ in intent.[17] Further, the Ordinance did not violate any novel implied constitutional guarantees or prohibitions,[18] and regardless, breach of a constitutional right did not give rise to a novel cause of action in damages outside contract or tort.[19] A majority did not consider whether the Constitution would limit genocidal legislation, a question left open to future litigation.[20] The decision also left open the possibility for damages regarding the misuse of powers under the Ordinance,[21] the court emphasising here that such misuse must be judged by the standards of the time, and not by contemporary standards.[22]
This possibility was taken up by the applicants in Cubillo v The Commonwealth.[23] Here, the Federal Court considered the same legislation as in Kruger. The applicants, Lorna Cubillo and Peter Gunner, claimed that, through their removal, the Commonwealth (through its agent, the Director of Native Affairs, by virtue of the doctrine of vicarious liability), committed the torts of negligence, false imprisonment and breach of statutory duty, and also breached its fiduciary duties owed to the applicants. Lorna Cubillo, was born in 1938 and at the age of seven she was forcibly removed by the Aborigines Inland Mission and the Native Affairs Branch to Retta Dixon Home in Darwin, where she remained until she was 18 years old. The second plaintiff, Peter Gunner, was born in 1948 on a pastoral station and was removed when he was about seven years old to St Mary’s Church of England Hostel in Alice Springs. He remained there until he was 16 years of age. Before Peter Gunner was removed in 1956 the trial judge described him being ‘part of a happy, healthy Aboriginal community and environment at Utopia Station’.[24] The Federal Court rejected the Commonwealth’s strike out application,[25] but decided against the plaintiffs on the merits of the case.[26] O’Loughlin J found there was insufficient evidence of a policy or practice of indiscriminate removal,[27] and no genocidal intent in either the legislation or its implementation by the Director of Native Affairs and others.[28] The Full Court of the Federal Court dismissed the appeal,[29] and the plaintiffs were denied leave to the High Court.[30]
The facts in Williams v The Minister, Aboriginal Land Rights Act 1983[31] were that Joy Williams was removed immediately after her mother had given birth and while being treated in hospital. Joy stayed in children’s homes until she was eighteen years old. She was removed under s 7(2) of the Aborigines Protection Act 1909 (NSW), which gave the Aborigines Welfare Board the power to take Joy under circumstances where the mother consented. She claimed that the removal caused her physical and psychological harm and she brought a number of claims, including breach of common law duty of care, breach of statutory duty, breach of fiduciary duty and false imprisonment. The trial and appeal judgments of the NSW Supreme Court found that Williams’ removal was lawful given the consent of the mother; the removal was in accordance with the Board’s statutory duty; the removal was for the purpose of improving the prospects of Williams,[32] and no common law duty of care arose because this would ‘cut across the whole statutory system for the protection of Aboriginal children’, opening the litigation gates too widely. [33]
On 25 December 1957, 13-month old Aboriginal infant Bruce Trevorrow was taken to the Children’s Hospital in Adelaide, suffering from a stomach complaint. Upon his discharge, and without the knowledge or consent of his parents, the Aborigines Protection Board (APB) placed him with a foster family. For the following ten years, he stayed with this family, during which time his mother unsuccessfully requested his return. In 1967, he was returned to live with her, however, within one year he was placed in a boy’s home, where he periodically remained until he turned 18. Trevorrow claimed that this separation from his natural family and the manner in which he was returned to his mother contributed to mental and physical health problems and a loss of cultural identity that continued throughout his adult life. He brought his case against the State on the grounds of misfeasance in public office, negligence, false imprisonment and breach of fiduciary duties, causes of action in respect of which the State denied any liability. Trevorrow also sought relief through damages and declarations. At trial, Gray J awarded $525,000 damages.[34] Of this amount, $75,000 was awarded as exemplary damages in respect of misfeasance in public office and false imprisonment, the State having acted ultra vires, cognisant of the unlawfulness of Trevorrow’s removal from his parents.[35]
The trial judgment includes a detailed overview of the statutory framework applicable to Bruce Trevorrow’s removal.[36] Gray J found that the legislative scheme applicable, covering moments of the plaintiff’s removal, placement and return, comprised the Aborigines Act 1934-1939 (SA), the Maintenance Act 1926-1937 (SA) and the Children’s Protection Act 1936 (SA). Central to the framework was s 10 of the Aborigines Act 1934, which provided that the APB was the ‘legal guardian’ of every Aboriginal child, notwithstanding that any such child had a living parent or other relative. The duties arising out of s 10 were set out in s 7. Justice Gray explained the key question as follows:

The question for determination in these proceedings is not whether such a policy existed, nor whether such a policy was lawful. ... [But whether] the State was bound to act in accordance with the terms of the relevant legislative scheme and in accordance with its fiduciary and other duties owed to the plaintiff and that, in breach of those requirements, it failed to do so.[37]

Accordingly, the organising legal question in Trevorrow differed from those questions considered in earlier Stolen Generations litigation, as it did not raise questions about the existence or lawfulness of a wider policy—the relevant question was much more limited, ‘more precise’.[38] One of the central issues was the nature of powers and duties that arose from the phrase ‘legal guardian’—whether, as the state contended, the APB’s role and responsibility as legal guardian of every child pursuant to s 10 of the Aborigines Act, meant that the APB was empowered to take any steps necessary to execute its duties, including the unrestricted power to remove an Aboriginal child from their parents.[39] The Court found that s 10 did not abrogate common law rights of parents in the absence of the manifestation of a clear intention to do so – for which the parliament had not expressed.[40] Therefore, s 10 did not give the Board the power to foster an Aboriginal child without the consent of the child’s parents.[41] Buti argues that the court ‘was imputed with the task of assessing the specific South Australian legislative scheme in relation to child removal and determining whether the government departments and entities complied with this scheme in their removal of the plaintiff’.[42] It is this, and the ‘conclusion that the state acted ultra vires by removing the plaintiff’ that influenced all aspects of Gray J’s findings, which implies that the decision may not have much impact beyond Bruce Trevorrow’s individual circumstances.[43]
Another significant distinction was the different characterisation of vicarious liability in Trevorrow. A threshold question in Lampard-Trevorrow and Cubillo Appeal was whether the State and Commonwealth respectively could be held liable for the acts of their officials. In terms of vicarious liability, in Cubillo Appeal, the Court approved O’Loughlan J’s invocation of the ‘independent discretion rule’ to prohibit imputing legal liability to the Commonwealth or the responsible Minister for breaches of guardianship duties by the Chief Protector of Aborigines.[44] The Commonwealth was accordingly held not to be vicariously responsible and therefore not liable for the acts of its employees, who exercised independent discretion in fulfilling their public duties. This approach to examining the liability of the Crown by reinforcing the ‘protected position of governments’ in litigation has been subject to criticism.[45]
In contrast, in Trevorrow, although the ‘independent discretion rule’ had been abrogated by statue, it has been noted that the tone of Gray J’s judgment would nonetheless indicate a strong judicial reluctance to countenance the State evading liability through the application of this rule.[46] Gray J accordingly found that the State was liable for the conduct of the APB or its Secretary. Similarly, in Lampard-Trevorrow, the Court found the APB to be an emanation of the State because it ‘acted for the benefit of the public and of the State’.[47] As the body that facilitated and funded the removal of Aboriginal children, the State was responsible for the acts of its officials in removing Trevorrow from his family. The Full Court accordingly upheld Gray J’s finding that the State is vicariously liable for the Secretary or APB’s tort of misfeasance in public office.
The evidence available also worked in Bruce Trevorrow’s favour, as there were documentary records supporting the limits of the state’s power, the breaches against Bruce Trevorrow, and also medical/departmental records available.[48] At trial, Gray J made a number of findings based on the oral evidence of Bruce’s siblings and half-siblings, and the state’s own medical and departmental records.[49] In contrast, much of the written record was missing by the time of the trials of Cubillo and Williams.[50] However, as Buti points out, it is not as though the plaintiffs in Cubillo and Williams did not have oral and documentary evidence to support their claims—rather, ‘the courts simply found the evidence presented by the state to be more persuasive’.[51] While it is true that there was a greater volume of evidence available for the court to consider in Trevorrow, including a significant state archive, Trevorrow signifies a change in the courts’ practices of interpreting historical evidence, as well as the ways in which the court framed this evidence in its conceptualisation of the legal categories—as we discuss below, these issues of law and interpretation of historical record are intimately linked—and these changes imply Trevorrow has significance beyond its factual-legal specificities. Most significantly, the courts had a different approach to the historical record. Second, the courts took a different approach to the legal categories involved in the claim from earlier claims, interpreting them in such a way that they applied to the situation of historical injuries arising out of the Stolen Generations. Third, the courts took a different, and critical approach to the contemporary standards in place at the time of the implementation of the policy, in contrast to earlier cases; and the courts also found that present-moment standards were relevant in evaluating certain aspects of the case. We would argue that the case’s innovations cannot be limited to its particular legal-factual matrix, primarily because they introduce methods of interpretation that open up the law to a new relationship to responsibility and the historical record. In the following section, we examine each of the elements of the appeal, comparing it to the trial judgment and previous litigation in relation to the Stolen Generations. In each, we pay particular attention to the interpretation of historical record, the role of consent, and the significance of the statutory regimes at issue.

PART III ISSUES ON APPEAL

B The State’s Liability for Misfeasance
Trevorrow was the first case in which a Stolen Generations litigant argued the tort of misfeasance in public office.[52] The Full Court was required to examine whether the State was liable for this tort in respect of Trevorrow’s removal. The authorities of Northern Territory v Mengel[53] and Sanders v Snell[54] define this tort to include acts by a public officer that he or she knows to be beyond his or her power and involve a foreseeable risk of harm.[55] For the purposes of the tort of misfeasance in public office, the APB and its Secretary were both found to be such officers exercising public powers pursuant to the public interest.[56] The APB had also been advised by the Crown Solicitor of the limits of its legal authority to remove Aboriginal children from their parents. In promoting its policy of removal, the APB was therefore found to have been generally cognisant that it was acting ultra vires. The Court accordingly found that the APB knew that it had no authority to remove Trevorrow without the necessary parental consent.

C False Imprisonment
False imprisonment is committed when someone ‘directly subjects another to total deprivation of freedom of movement without lawful justification [or consent]’.[57] It is a powerful avenue for Stolen Generations litigants because it does not depend on the government acting negligently or breaching a statute. Rather, it arises because the plaintiff has his or her liberty restricted. The potential for a successful claim in false imprisonment was demonstrated in the trial judgment of Cubillo, where the Court found that Lorna Cubillo had a prima facie case against the Director of Native Affairs for false imprisonment. However, the claim failed because the Commonwealth was held not to be vicariously liable for the Director’s actions. Again in the trial judgment of Trevorrow, false imprisonment was made out based on a reading of the common law requirements in UK jurisprudence.[58]
However, the South Australian Court of Appeal in Lampard-Trevorrow overturned this finding through a narrow reading of ‘imprisonment’, in a way that was anomalous to the contextual approach it took to other aspects of its reasoning – including consent. To begin with, the court held that, based on the cases of Meering v Grahame-White Aviation Co Ltd[59] and Murray v Ministry of Defence[60] it was not necessary to establish the detainee’s awareness of his or her detention nor physical capacity to exercise freedom of movement.[61] To determine whether Trevorrow was subject to false imprisonment, the Court found that the central issue was whether he was subject to a total deprivation of freedom of movement in the absence of lawful authority. The Court reasoned that the element of total restraint was not made out in the present case, as any restraint during Trevorrow’s placement with the foster family was attributable to his young age and the family’s ensuing obligation to care for him. While in foster care, Trevorrow experienced freedom of movement equal to that of other children of a like age, subject only to normal restrictions placed on children.[62] The Court accordingly reversed Gray J’s finding of liability for wrongful detention.
The court found that the care and protection given by the carer of a child is not a deprivation of the child’s liberty. The Court of Appeal reasoned that Bruce Trevorrow ‘was able to move about (once he reached a certain age) as he wished subject only to the normal limits placed on children’ and was ‘not imprisoned within a defined area’ by his foster parents beyond the normal control of parents.[63] The Bench stated:

It might be added that if this is a case of total restraint or total deprivation of freedom of movement, then all small children are, as a matter of fact, equally subject to the same restraint. ... Bruce Trevorrow, when fostered by Mrs Davies, had the same freedom of movement, or absence of freedom as the case may be, as other children of a like age.[64]

However, this is a very narrow and artificial reading of freedom of movement—one in which the court is not comparing like circumstances with like. The issue was not whether, once handed over to the foster parents, those parents restrained Bruce Trevorrow in a way that was unusual for a small child to be restrained (after all, a kidnapper could also set a child up in a house and treat them as any other child might be kept, but this does not take away from the fact that there has been an initial act of kidnapping—it is this act, and not the after-care, which should matter to a legal interpretation). Rather, the issue was whether the removal itself could be interpreted as an act of restraint. The Court did not appreciate that non-Aboriginal children of Bruce Trevorrow’s age would have had the freedom to be with their parents. It is only because of the policy of the Stolen Generations that Trevorrow was denied this freedom. The Court drew unfitting analogies with restraint in childcare centres, stating, ‘Most childcare centres have substantial fences and a gate that children cannot open’.[65] In this acontextual reading, the Court was not addressing the liberty denied to Bruce Trevorrow to be with his parents due to the policy of Aboriginal child removal. In other words, an Aboriginal child’s forcible restraint from his parents and against his parents’ wishes was regarded as the same as a non-Aboriginal person who lived with his parents and was not subject to the Stolen Generations policy. As discussed below, the Court in Lampard-Trevorrow explicitly acknowledged the problems with consent and this had legal effect. However, the Court stopped short of recognising that non-consent to removal might be a form of restraint on the child, that is, a restraint to be with his or her parents.

D Breach of Fiduciary Duty
The Court further considered whether the APB’s failure to inform Trevorrow of the unlawfulness of his removal and provide him with access to legal advice constituted a breach of fiduciary duty. In previous Stolen Generations cases, arguments contending breaches of fiduciary duty have largely not been successful. In Williams v Minister, Aboriginal Land Rights Act 1983, Abadee J denied a fiduciary claim similar to that in Lampard-Trevorrow, reasoning that the protection of non-economic interests, such as duties of guardianship, could not be warranted under Australian fiduciary law.[66] In contrast to Williams, Gray J in Trevorrow imposed fiduciary duties, which encompassed an obligation to inform Trevorrow of the circumstances of his removal and facilitate access to legal advice regarding the State’s conduct.[67]
However, the court in Lampard-Trevorrow closed the door opened in Trevorrow by a narrow reading of fiduciary obligations. It agreed with the trial judge that the APB was Trevorrow’s legal guardian and Trevorrow was its ward, as provided for under s 10 of the Aborigines Act 1934 (SA) (‘the 1934 Act’), and therefore a fiduciary relationship existed.[68] It held that the APB’s relationship ‘with Aboriginal children generally’ did not give rise to a ‘wide reaching fiduciary duty’.[69] This would result in a duty being ‘owed to all Aboriginal children’ fostered by the APB, which would be inconsistent with the provisions of the 1934 Act.[70] It was persuaded by Brennan CJ’s observation in Breen v Williams that ‘it is erroneous to regard the duty owed by a fiduciary to his beneficiary as attaching to every aspect of the fiduciary’s conduct’.[71] The court enunciated policy-based reasons for excluding a broad duty: that the APB was funded by Parliamentary appropriation and ‘could do only what its resources permitted.[72] Further, a wide-ranging duty was inconsistent with the purpose of the Aborigines Act 1934 (SA), and ‘would transform its role in a manner not contemplated by the 1934 Act’.[73] The APB might be subject to a fiduciary duty to Trevorrow, but only where the ‘particular situation was one that attracted one of the recognised fiduciary duties’ and was consistent with the 1934 Act.[74]
By establishing that not all circumstances arising from the relationship between the APB and Trevorrow ‘are to be resolved in terms of a fiduciary duty’, the court failed to deal effectively with any of them. It gave the analogy with Gaudron and McHugh JJ’s point in Breen v Williams that a doctor does not have a fiduciary obligation to inform a patient of negligence or breach of contract.[75] But in making this analogy the court omits the distinguishing facts that Trevorrow was a minor and confined in state care without the resources or capacities akin to a patient who has been wronged. The court finally reasoned that imposing a fiduciary duty could have resulted in the ‘oddity’ where the APB discharged its duty by informing the plaintiff that it acted unlawfully and assisting him obtain legal advice, and then sat back and left him in custody.[76] This circuitous logic suggests that a fiduciary duty cannot arise because of the removal and the removal is lawful because there is no duty. It would be akin to a police officer refusing a defendant the right to legal advice in relation to his/her custody because of the fact of his/her custody at the hands of the police. In the same vein, the obligation to provide such advice to a removed child who would be detained for a decade would not appear to be an onerous burden. The Court, however, found that, in failing to advise Trevorrow of the wrongfulness of his removal and provide him with legal advice, the State did not fail to observe any fiduciary duties.


E Negligence
The Full Court further examined whether the APB owed Bruce Trevorrow a duty of care to avoid causing him psychiatric injury, and whether this duty was breached when it placed Trevorrow with a foster family, failed to adequately supervise this process and in due course returned him to his mother without due preparation.[77]
In Williams Appeal, policy reasons, principally concerns regarding floodgate litigation, militated against the imposition of a duty of care in such institution-child relationships.[78] The Court was particularly attuned to possible economic consequences that may result from a decision that renders the government liable for acts committed against Stolen Generation litigants. However, in Trevorrow, Gray J rejected the argument that recognising a duty of care would expose the State to indeterminate liability. This analysis substantially deviates from the rather guarded reasoning in Williams Appeal and Cubillo Appeal.[79] Applying the salient features test, Gray J found that the State owed Trevorrow a duty of care in relation to his removal, placement with a foster family and return to his natural mother, a duty that was breached.[80] Similarly, in Lampard-Trevorrow, the Court was also prepared to find against the State in negligence. Following the underlying principle identified by McHugh J in Crimmins v Stevedoring Industry Finance Committee that ‘no common law duty of care can be imposed on the statutory authority if to do so is... forbidden by the relevant Act,’[81] their Honours first considered whether the imposition of a common law duty of care to avoid causing harm to Trevorrow was inconsistent with the 1934 Act. The Court concluded that the imposition of such a duty would not be inconsistent with the obligations under this statutory scheme, as both promote the protection and welfare of Aborigines and Aboriginal children.[82] Section 10 of the 1934 Act namely requires the APB to act in the best interests of Aboriginal children, reflecting the APB’s role as the ‘legal guardian’ of these children.[83] This obligation does not impose duties that are contrary to the postulated common law duty to avoid causing Trevorrow foreseeable harm. The Full Court noted that ‘to require that reasonable care be taken to avoid injury to the child... is not opposed to or inconsistent with the statutory requirement. It complements it’.[84]
Second, the Court considered whether the harm caused to Trevorrow was reasonably foreseeable. Their Honours concluded that the APB knew of the risk of separating a mother and child, as contemporaneous research indicated that this process may be detrimental to a child’s wellbeing. Although welfare officers at the time may not have foreseen the specific harm caused by Trevorrow’s removal, they possessed a general understanding that failure to maintain contact with Trevorrow’s natural family may cause him harm—here, the Court relied on the evidence adduced at trial, based on medical opinion, the oral evidence of welfare officers and a substantial body of literature, including publications available during the period of the plaintiff’s removal. This evidence confirmed the risk of harm to a child deprived of maternal care and affection available during the 1950s and 1960s.[85] The Court concluded that a reasonable person would have examined the likelihood of such harm occurring and would have removed Trevorrow from his mother only if remaining in her custody would have presented a greater risk.[86] However, the APB failed to make reasonable enquiries into the circumstances of the Trevorrow family and the infant’s physical state before placing him with foster parents. By failing to make these enquiries before removing him, the APB was found to be in breach of its duty of care.[87]

F Limitation Period
As Trevorrow did not bring proceedings within the specified time limit, a further issue for the Full Court was to determine whether the discretion to extend the period of limitation under s 48 of the Limitation of Actions Act 1936 (SA) should have been exercised. Under s 48(1), a court may extend the time prescribed for a particular cause of action as the justice of the case may require. Under s 48(3)(b), an extension of time may only be granted where facts material to a plaintiff’s case are not ascertained by him or her within time, or the plaintiff’s failure to institute timely actions resulted from the conduct of the defendant.
Statutory limitation periods applying to claims in negligence and wrongful imprisonment may present a substantial obstacle to the success of Stolen Generation litigation. In Cubillo Trial, despite finding that the plaintiff established the requisite conditions for a time extension to be granted, the Federal Court ultimately considered that there would be overwhelming prejudice to the Commonwealth’s case if this discretion were to be exercised.[8] In this case, the ‘effluxion of time had so prejudiced the defence of the Commonwealth that it could not obtain a fair trial’.[88] This conclusion was reached even though the Court made positive findings of fact regarding much of Cubillo’s claim.[89] The insufficiency of documentary evidence and testimony due to the passing of time was particularly determinative in reaching this decision.[90] Considerations of fairness, certainty and public policy were also significant. The Court opined that it is in the wider public interest to promote finality in litigation and that it would be undesirable to subject potential defendants to an indefinite possibility of legal action.
In contrast, the Court in Lampard-Trevorrow upheld the decision to grant an extension of time under s 48(1) of the Limitations of Actions Act 1936 (SA).[91] In considering the discretion to grant an extension, the Court considered McHugh J’s observation in Sola Optical Australia Pty Ltd v Mills that the purpose of exercising such discretion is primarily ‘to eliminate the injustice a prospective plaintiff might suffer by reason of the imposition of a rigid time limit within which an action was to be commenced’.[92] The Court was persuaded that any prejudice caused to the State by virtue of the inability of criticised individuals to defend themselves would be outbalanced by the injustice that the plaintiff would experience if the claim were to be time-barred. A significant factor in this reasoning was that, as early as 1977, the APB’s successor had information that the APB removed Trevorrow without statutory authority. Without the disclosure of this information, the Court regarded Trevorrow’s failure to institute his action within the time limit as understandable, the APB having contributed to this delay.[93] The Court further considered it to be in the wider public interest that members of the Stolen Generation are able to have their claims decided by the judiciary and stressed the importance of taking judicial notice of this ‘matter of national concern and controversy’.[94] It was this final consideration that ultimately ‘tilted the scales in favour of the discretion being exercised to grant an extension of time’.[95]

G Procedural Fairness
Although the doctrine of procedural fairness had not been identified when the APB removed Trevorrow, the Full Court held that it should nevertheless be applied to the current case.[96] In Kioa v West, Mason J articulated the authoritative statement of this doctrine:

there is a common law duty to act fairly, in the sense of according procedural fairness in the making of administrative decisions which affect rights, interests and legitimate expectations, subject only to the clear manifestation of a contrary statutory intention.[97]

Trevorrow’s parents possessed a common law right to be heard prior to the APB making any adverse findings affecting their son. This right stemmed from their status as Bruce’s natural parents as well as the significant interest they possessed in continuing to maintain custody of him.[98] As was the case in Annetts v McCann and J v Lieschke, the Court in Lampard-Trevorrow considered that the obligation to afford procedural fairness to parents of a child arises not only from their rights and interests as parents, but also from their child’s interests.[99] Trevorrow’s parents’ right to be heard therefore also derived from Bruce’s interest in them retaining custody of him.[100] In recognising the importance of providing a hearing in such circumstances, the Court referred to Brennan J’s statement in J v Lieschke that ‘it would offend the deepest human sentiments as well as a basic legal principle to permit a court to take a child form its parents without hearing the parents’.[101]
In the present case, there was neither urgency that required the APB to act before contacting Trevorrow’s parents, nor was there substantial difficulty in locating them to conduct a hearing. Therefore, although no formal hearing was required, the Court found that the APB did not fulfil its obligation to notify Trevorrow’s parents of its intended arrangements and failed to provide an adequate opportunity for them to respond to the APB’s proposed course of action, ultimately denying them their right to procedural fairness.

PART IV IMPLICATIONS: THE INTERPRETATION OF EVIDENCE AND A NEW RELATIONSHIP TO HISTORY
In their book, Rights and Redemption, Curthoys, Genovese and Reilly discuss the increasing role of historians as experts in Indigenous litigation involving historical wrongs. They point to the importance of the disciplines of law and history to talk to one another in these cases.[102] The expertise of historians was drawn on, across the Stolen Generations cases discussed; it is only in the Trevorrow Cases that a contextualised understanding of the historical evidence has legal effect. Previously, for instance, in Cubillo Trial the Federal Court pointed to evidence that ‘showed that there were people in the 1940s and 1950s who cared for the Aboriginal people’ and were ‘acting in the best interests of the child’.[103] It held,

[T]he evidence does not deny the existence of the stolen generation and there was some evidence that some part Aboriginal children were taken into institutions against the wishes of their parents. However, I am limited to making findings on the evidence that was presented to this Court in these proceedings: that evidence does not support a finding that there was any policy of removal of part-Aboriginal children such as that alleged by the applicants; and if, contrary to that finding, there was such a policy, the evidence in these proceedings would not justify a finding that it was ever implemented as a matter of course in respect of these applicants.[104]


The Federal Court’s reading of the legal archive does not result in a finding of the non-existence of the Stolen Generations, but leads it to an evidentiary problem: ‘not enough evidence to decide’.[105] This problem was compounded by the presumption in favour of the state’s own archive.[106] It is also possible to criticise the grounds upon which the finding was found. For example, van Krieken is critical of the court using the fact that there was no policy to remove all children, and the lack of capacity to fully implement the policy, as being grounds for denying the existence of the policy and argues that ‘the mere selective application of a policy does not render its existence logically impossible’.[107]
The decontextualised reading of the evidence is brought into sharp relief in relation to the issue of consent to the child removals in Cubillo Trial. The court construed a thumbprint, purportedly that of Cubillo’s mother, on a document as evidence of parental consent to the removal of her daughter. In referring to consent in his construction of compliance with s 6, O’Loughlin J noted that ‘there was no way of knowing whether the thumb mark on the ‘Form of Consent’ was [Mr Gunner’s mother’s]; even on the assumption that it was, there was no way of knowing whether [she] understood the contents of the document’.[108] However, the court gave the government officers the benefit of doubt:

it is not beyond the realms of imagination to find that it was possible for a dedicated, well-meaning patrol officer to explain to a tribal Aboriginal such as [Mr Gunner’s mother] the meaning and effect of the document. I have no mandate to assume that [Mr Gunner’s mother] did not apply her thumb or that she, having applied her thumb, did not understand the meaning and effect of the document.[109]

Therefore, the documentary record was found to prevail. This is surprising given that, on its way to finding that the issue of consent did not go ‘to the heart’ of the trial,[110] the Federal Court made a number of findings regarding the ways in which parental consent was used to assist in, and even ‘produced’ by, removal policies. The court rejected submissions made on behalf of the Commonwealth that some or all of the parents had initiated their children’s removal by asking the Native Affairs Branch or Aborigines Inland Mission to provide their children with a better education and better standard of living.[111] The court found that evidence did not establish consent was generally obtained by the Native Affairs Branch in the removal of the children at Phillip Creek, of whom Mrs Cubillo was one.[112] Although making no formal finding on the matter, the court found that the evidence (including the behaviour of the mothers, the evidence of three Tennant Creek women and the limited time available to explain the process of removal) suggested that ‘some, if not all, of the children may well have been taken without their mothers’ consent’.[113] In fact, the court was ‘unable to make a finding that any of the mothers gave their informed consents to the removal of their children’.[114] Therefore, the court rejected the Commonwealth’s argument that consent had been generally given. However, where there was documentary evidence of a thumbprint he favoured the assumption that consent was informed. Although the court demonstrated an appreciation of historical context, it was not applied to interpreting legal sources.
It is significant that the Federal Court examined the operation of consent more generally than the circumstances surrounding the particular plaintiffs, and demonstrated that ‘consent’ was not an untroubled concept. The court questioned the nature and quality of consent, and the power relationship that produced consent, by referring to evidence that showed that the practices of the Director in obtaining consent included processes of ‘educating and preparing mothers’ for separation.[115] The implication here, of course, is that any final and formal consent can be seen as an end-effect of these processes of coercive ‘education’. The court also questioned whether sufficient consent can be deemed to have been given by parents, considering the stringent time constraints under which the information was purportedly provided.[116]
Ultimately, however, the Federal Court found that the documents reflected Topsy’s informed consent. It took for granted that the relevant information was given in the correct language, and the effectiveness of a government education program in relation to removals. By contrast, in the Trevorrow Cases, the South Australian courts expressed a distrust concerning the documentary record regarding consent, and used a practice of interpretation that considered general practices relating to consent (and its documentation) in evaluating the particular document at issue.[117]
It is significant that, as discussed below, the problematic operation of consent, especially questions relating to its authenticity, has been noted by the courts, although these observations had no legal effect prior to the Trevorrow Cases. These problems have been recorded widely by historians. Trish Luker researched the processes by which problematic evidence was accepted in support of parental consent in the Cubillo case—the choice and shaping of facts, and the interpretation of evidence.[118] The courts’ approach to interpreting documentary evidence in Cubillo failed to adequately acknowledge the power disparity between the APB and Aboriginal persons as well as the wider historical and social context in which many Aboriginal parents, namely Cubillo’s mother, were not literate in English,[119] and were therefore unlikely to have understood the content and implications of relevant documentation.[120]
In contrast, in the Trevorrow Cases, the courts demonstrated different views of history and the role of state power, issues which are bound up with the interpretation of evidence. In determining the issue of consent, the Full Court agreed with the trial judge and interpreted the continued requests of Trevorrow’s mother that her son be returned as an indication that the requisite parental consent was absent.[121] The State of South Australia submitted that the trial judge was wrong to find that neither parent consented to Bruce Trevorrow’s placement with Mrs Davies, and here it relied mainly on missing documentation concerning the removal. The Court of Appeal acknowledged that documents were missing, but found that consent had not been given – significantly, in doing so, it relied on evidence concerning general practices concerning consent, as well as evidence concerning Trevorrow’s particular case. While the court in Cubillo referred to similar general practices, its finding in relation to Peter Gunner’s mother’s consent was based on the documentary evidence alone. The significance of the court’s interpretation in Lampard-Trevorrow is that it is an acknowledgment of the importance of context in the historical operation and legal interpretation of consent. It is significant that the Court of Appeal was willing to look critically at documents presented as evidence, and did not interpret the absence of documents as necessarily favouring the state’s position. The court rejected the state’s submission that a missing file may have contained the records of the almoner testifying to the consensual removal of the plaintiff, arguing, through an evaluation of the context of the records, that the time constraints and role of the almoner made it unlikely that the records would include a document concerning consent.[122] Of greater significance was the Court’s questioning of the role of documentary evidence. The Court found that this evidence should not necessarily be privileged:

There is no reason why, in principle, the documentary records should be preferred to the oral evidence. Everything depends upon the facts of the case. In the present case it needs to be borne in mind that documentary records are not to be assumed to be reliable.[123]

This is of great significance in Stolen Generations cases where the archives contain gaps, and in which those documents that do exist need to be interpreted in the context in which they were produced.
The Court in Lampard-Trevorrow took into account historical context when interpreting the facts to hand. Based on an analysis of correspondence concerning other cases, the Court found that ‘the requirement to obtain parental consent was not always observed’.[124] The Court based this conclusion on a number of documents. A letter dated 12 August 1958 from the Secretary of the APB to the officer in charge at the Oodnadatta Police Station stated:

If the parents of these children have not already consented in writing for the United Aborigines Mission to care and control the children until a certain age, then I suggest that you endeavour to obtain the consent of the parents on the forms enclosed.

In confidence, you will certainly realise that in any case this consent form is not a legal document, and should it be that the parents remove the children from the care of the Mission or the Board, no legal action could be taken to regain control of the children.[125]

Another document, a letter of 16 October 1958 written by the Secretary of the APB to the Superintendent of Aborigines Welfare in Victoria, stated: ‘Again in confidence, for some years without legal authority, the Board have taken charge of many aboriginal children’.[126] In a letter dated 19 May 1960 to Pastor Eckermann, the Secretary of the APB stated:

For your information only I have to inform you that legally, I have no right to remove a child from its parents. However, in such cases I do so and where deemed necessary we refuse to allow the child to be returned to its’ parents without my consent.

If you so desire you can inform the mother of the child that it has been placed in your Children’s Home at my direction and cannot be released to the mother without my written consent. You should add that I will not likely consent to the children being released until such time as the mother is properly accommodated and able and willing to care for the child in a proper manner.[127]

Here the Court concluded:

the Secretary of the APB is informing Pastor Eckermann, ‘off the record’ that on occasions he has removed and will remove a child from its parents, without parental consent, and will subsequently refuse to allow the child to be returned to the parents, unless satisfied that the proposed living arrangements are suitable.[128]

The last paragraph quoted above ‘contemplates a bluff being used to enable the APB to keep the child in question under its control’.[129]
It is in the context of this understanding that the Court of Appeal read a letter the Board sent to Thora Karpany in 1958, which was sent in response to her inquiry about Bruce. The letter stated that Bruce was still undergoing medical treatment, and the Court found this statement, and the implication that Bruce could therefore not be returned to her, ‘dissembling’.[130] Even if Thora Karpany had consented to Bruce Trevorrow being fostered, such consent did not legally authorise Bruce’s permanent removal – and the Secretary of the Board knew of Thora’s entitlement to have Bruce returned to her. Here we have the Court explicitly acknowledging the problematic role of consent in the practice of removal – problems that were intimated in Cubillo, but which in Lampard-Trevorrow are labelled as ‘a pretence of power’.[131]
Although the Appeal Court acknowledged the possibility that consent was obtained ‘by one of the now unavailable witnesses, and ... placed in one of the missing files’, the Court found that the trial judge’s conclusion of non-consent was supported by significant evidence.[132] First, there was no documentation of consent in Bruce Trevorrow’s file. Second, there was no reliable reference to consent being given in other documents. Third, there was evidence that:

when necessary, in the perceived interests of a child, the [Board] would place a child in an institution or with a foster family without parental consent, using a pretence of power (which undoubtedly would have been effective) and, if appropriate, using an element of bluff or deception.[133]

This last point is significant since here the South Australian Court of Appeal referred to the general context of practices and policies in which consent was made – taking a very different approach to interpretation from that used in Cubillo Trial, where the Federal Court noted the evidence of general policies but in making its findings insisted on narrowing its focus to the particular circumstances of the applicants.[134] In contrast, the court in Lampard-Trevorrow found that, ‘The reliance on medical advice in response to Thora Karpany’s letter to the [Board] of 25 July 1958 is consistent with the use of a bluff to deflect her request’.[135]
The Stolen Generations cases challenge the courts to interpret doctrines of tort and equity so that they recognise the historical harms arising out of past policies and practices.[136] This process or conceptual re-thinking needs to occur in context—as Lampard-Trevorrow demonstrates, it requires interpretive practices on the part of the courts that involve a new relationship to evidence, history, and the significance of contemporary standards. These practices have consequences for law’s role in determining responsibility for historical harms. Australian critical historiography has been central to the re-framing of key narratives in law and the public sphere, especially concerning the centrality of violence to the formation of the Australian nation-state. These practices, Genevose argues, have revealed that ‘nation-building was inseparable from genocidal intent’.[137] Genovese positions Australian critical historiography as ‘a conceptual “redemption”’,[138] a concept that was developed by Curthoys et al.[139] Key to redemption is first, the recognition by the public sphere of a different role of the state in regards to past violence and dispossession of Indigenous Australians, from that which had previously been accepted; and second, commitments by the public to engagement, ‘reparative action and acceptance of moral culpability ... on questions of accountability for the past in the present’.[140]
In Cubillo Trial, following a ‘painstaking examination of a large body of historical material and oral testimony’,[141] the court asked whether the Commonwealth had acted unreasonably or otherwise through the Aboriginal Protection Board, and concluded that there was no evidence that they had done so.[142] In arriving at this decision, the court rejected evidence that there was social criticism of the practice of child removal, instead preferring the evidence of the state’s own archive.[143] Significantly, community standards were explicitly rejected as a source of authority for this finding. Despite establishing that those who removed the children would ‘stand condemned by today’s standards,’[144] and that ‘subsequent events have shown that they were wrong,’[145] the court held these contemporary standards were not relevant to deciding liability, as ‘it would be erroneous ... to hold that a step taken in purported exercise of a statutory discretionary power was taken unreasonably ... if the unreasonableness appears only from a change in community standards.’[146] Ultimately, the court found that there was insufficient evidence to determine a number of questions about the removal policies.
In contrast, the South Australian Supreme Court in Trevorrow found that standards of evaluation in the present moment were relevant to deciding the issue of damages. The court noted, as courts had in earlier cases, including Kruger, (but to no legal effect), the following:

The existence of the policy of removing Aboriginal children from their families and the detrimental long term effects of that policy on both those removed and the wider Aboriginal community, is now widely recognized in the community, and was previously the subject of judicial recognition.[147]

Community standards became relevant in the award for exemplary damages, appropriate only where the defendant’s conduct ‘calls for manifest disapprobation by the community and that it must attract something more than compensation ...’.[148] The Supreme Court found that Trevorrow’s case gave rise to an award of exemplary damages, based on the initial act of removal, the failure to return Trevorrow to his mother, and the state’s failure to inform Trevorrow both of the circumstances of his removal, and the rights arising from that fact.[149] In doing so, the court ‘uses the damages award to reflect upon the concept of redemption inherent in our own contemporary standards’.[150] This provides a way for the law to ‘acknowledge its role in political questions and state practices instead of seeing them as separate or distinct’,[151] as they were perceived in earlier Stolen Generations cases. The law can do this by taking seriously a ‘democratic conception of authority that compels the state, through its law, as well as through international law, to take the idea of contemporaneous standards—and reparation—seriously’,[152] as is done in the court’s award of exemplary damages. The Full Court of the South Australian Supreme Court, in upholding the trial decision to grant Bruce Trevorrow an extension of time to bring his claim, held that ‘there is a definite public interest in persons like Bruce Trevorrow being able to have their claims decided by a court’ and that ‘public interest, in this context, is a question of justice’.[153]

PART V: THE ‘MYTH’ OF CONSENT
Consent has been a significant issue in all Stolen Generations cases, but The Trevorrow Cases not only made consent central to its findings—it also raised questions about the problematic nature of consent itself, problems that had been flagged in earlier cases but which had never affected the legal outcome previous to Trevorrow Cases. In the Williams cases,[154] consent was key to whether Joy Williams’ removal at birth constituted false imprisonment; in Cubillo Trial,[155] consent was not determinative to claims in negligence due to the broad scope of the statute granting the Welfare Board powers to remove children, but was nonetheless argued in defence by the Government, and found to be significant as a factor in determining the proper use of statutory power, and in the Trevorrow Cases,[156] consent was discussed both in relation to negligence and false imprisonment. Consent has been a central issue in Stolen Generations cases for two main reasons: first, it formed part of the factual archive due to the widespread practice of officials seeking parental consent to expedite the process of removal; and second, the state has used parental consent to bar actions in trespass or false imprisonment. Therefore, the procurement of consent has had a doubly wicked effect, because it was used to both justify expedient removals and then subsequently put as a legal justification to deny compensation on the basis that the mother had given away her child.
In Cubillo Appeal the Full Federal Court displayed an approach to identifying consent that was less favourable to the plaintiff. As discussed above, the Court interpreted the evidence in ways that failed to acknowledge the historical operation of consent (and the associated creation of documents) in the context of the removal of children. The issue of consent to removal was at the heart of the Commonwealth’s legal argument against Lorna Napanangka Cubillo and Peter Gunner. Essentially, the Commonwealth sought to recharacterise the act of removal as consensual and thereby authorised by the parents. In Lorna Cubillo’s case, the court found that the issue determining legislative authority to remove her under s 6 of the Aboriginals Ordinance was not one of consent. Rather, it was whether the Director of Native Affairs held the opinion that it was ‘necessary or desirable’ to undertake her ‘care, custody or control’.[157] Ultimately, the court acknowledged that the Director properly used his authority under the legislation. In Peter Gunner’s case, it was found that questions relating to consent, were not the ‘correct question[s] to ask’ in legally characterising the act of removal – rather, the key question was ‘the reason for his removal’ – so that, ‘it would not matter by what persons or by what means that removal was effected, if his removal was effected within the terms of ss 6 or 16 of the Aboriginals Ordinance’.[158] Nonetheless, parental consent was one matter that was taken into account in assessing whether the legislation had been properly applied.
In Lampard-Trevorrow, parental non-consent was important to both the factual and legal findings. Factually, the court found no consent had been given. Legally, non-consent became central to the court’s interpretation of the state’s failure to properly execute its statutory authority and assume control of Trevorrow. The court considered whether s 10 of the 1934 Act conferred upon the APB the power to foster Aboriginal children without parental consent and, if that right existed, whether it was validly exercised in the present case. The state contended that, by virtue of its role under s 10 as ‘the legal guardian of every Aboriginal child,’[159] the APB was authorised to remove Aboriginal children from their parents to protect the children’s interests. The court was persuaded that the purpose of the 1934 Act was to protect Indigenous people and provide them with financial and educational assistance.[160] However, in considering Gleeson CJ’s ration in Plaintiff S157/2000 v The Commonwealth, that ‘courts do not impute to the legislature an intention to abrogate fundamental rights or freedoms unless such an intention is clearly manifested by unmistaken and unambiguous language,’[161] the Full Court concluded that s 10 did not imbue the APB with the ability to remove Aboriginal children from their parents without consent.[162] Giving s 10 such a wide interpretation would deprive Aboriginal parents of their right to the custody of their children.
The Full Court found that it was the state’s failure to acknowledge the parent’s authority (and therefore the lack of consent to Trevorrow’s removal) that led, in part, to the state’s liability. The Court found that s 10 of the 1934 Act, which provided that the APB was ‘the legal guardian of every Aboriginal child’ was ambiguous.[163] It found that the legislation did not abrogate fundamental rights in the absence of the manifestation of a clear intention to do so.[164] Therefore, s 10 did not give the Board the power to foster an Aboriginal child without the consent of the child’s parents. This finding of non-consent was fundamental: it enabled the court to convey that the removal was forced, and provided a basis for a breach of law. Therefore, not only was there forcible removal, (a fact that had been established in earlier cases),[165] but this removal was legally wrong.
Consent was also a central issue in the claim of false imprisonment in the first Stolen Generations case, Williams Trial.[166] The NSW Supreme Court emphasised the mother’s consent to removal at the time of the birth of her daughter, (although the fact of this consent was contested by Joy), and ruled against false imprisonment on that basis.[167] The court stated that there was no false imprisonment because the Welfare Board ‘had lawful control over the plaintiff’ due to the consent of the mother.[168] In reviewing the case, the NSW Court of Appeal adverted to the problematic nature of consent, but chose to treat consent as proven by virtue of the documentary evidence of the application. The court held:

One part of the plaintiff’s case at trial depended on the proposition that she had been removed from her mother without her mother’s consent. It was this which underlay the claims of false imprisonment ... This part of the case failed because ... the plaintiff was lawfully admitted to the control of the Board on the application of her mother ...[169]

The National Inquiry into the Separation of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Children from Their Families revealed the hollow meaning of parental consent in child removal. Consent was a veil for the forced removal of Aboriginal children and was uninformed if not coerced. In its report, Bringing them Home, a Tasmanian Stolen Generations survivor described his mother’s capacity to consent in the following way: ‘[Mum] could not read or write, and obviously would not have understood the implications of what she was signing’.[170] The Report found that ‘mothers who had just given birth were coerced to relinquish their newborn babies’.[171] The Report identified that acquiring consent operated to circumvent official proof of neglect. Bringing them Home noted, ‘If parents could be ‘persuaded’ to consent to the removal of their children the Board did not have to show that a child was neglected or uncontrollable’.[172] When Indigenous parents refused to consent, the Aboriginal and Welfare Boards overpowered their agency. Parents ‘were told they would have to leave the stations and would be denied rations’.[173] Police officers told young mothers that ‘if they did not consent to the adoption of their babies the father of the child would be prosecuted for carnal knowledge’.[174] Alongside this was an ideological campaign to make parents feel guilty that they could not offer them the opportunities of the ‘outside world’.[175] This is despite contemporary evidence and theory that children who were not removed performed much better in life than those who were removed.
The significance of narratives of consent to the achievement of legal and social justice goes beyond the success of any single claim, as significant as such a claim may be. Saidiya Hartman suggests that there is a relationship between consent and subjection, and that the State’s use of consent in dealing with the subjected may act to disguise the ‘condition of violent domination’ that actually operates between subjector and subjected.[176] Writing about the legal context of racial subjugation during slavery and its aftermath in the United States of America, Hartman argues that consent became ‘intelligible only as submission’.[177] In the Australian context, non-‘whiteness’ has historically been a point of reference for structural inferiority in Australia, according to Ghassan Hage.[178] Yet the law nonetheless assumes consent as capable of being equally afforded by Indigenous and non-Indigenous people. The historical impossibility of consent in the context of forced subjection is usually not disentangled, explored, or even ‘seen’ by the courts.
In Stolen Generations cases, assumptions that ‘whites’ could better care for children underlie the implication of parental complicity in the Indigenous child removals. These assumptions were taught to and at times appropriated by Aboriginal parents – who were then seen as succumbing to the system’s logic. As Hartman suggests, power can become defined by these manipulations to present a picture of reciprocation, rather than acts of domination.[179] It allowed the state to be presented as a benevolent institution rather than a terrorising one. But there is a further sinister side to the domination, which is always on guard when manipulations falter. When parents failed to comply with the removal of their children, they would attract reprisals from state agents – with consequences that included being reported to police, losing employment or experiencing physical violence.[180]
Although courts surveyed and sometimes accepted evidence of the problematic operation of consent in Stolen Generations cases, prior to the Trevorrow Cases, they essentially treated consent as an individual act freely and voluntarily given. The use of consent in this way turned the state’s act of removal into a parental act, thereby transforming ‘relations of violence and domination into those of affinity’.[181] The fiction of consent suggests that the powerless had agency and strength, and that there is an ‘ostensible equality between the dominant and the dominated’,[182] while at the same time concealing the actual powerlessness of the subjected. These judicial narratives further impute that Indigenous peoples are unwilling to care for their own children, and reaffirms the fiction that the caring and nurturing of children is the domain of ‘whites’, thereby undermining the role of the Indigenous family. But here there is a further irony – that Aboriginal consent is predicated on the presumption of civility, and yet Aboriginal people are denied this virtue because of their role as neglectful parents.
The nature of the evidence of consent, and how consent was acquired, have been questioned by academics and legal practitioners. Anna Cody, who was a solicitor on the case, commented that Joy Williams ‘was taken away from her mother when she was a few hours old. Any mother who’s had a baby would question exactly how much she could consent to giving a baby away when she’s just a few hours old’.[183] Chris Cunneen and Julia Grix argue that the NSW Supreme Court’s comment that the mother may have forgotten whether she had consented reveal an ‘extraordinary lack of insight into the issues of consent and the power of the [Board] over Aboriginal persons’.[184] Another issue that was raised by the court to inculcate the mother in the removal was that the mother did not attempt to release the child from foster care. This presumes that she knew that she had this option available to her, had the material means to pursue such a course, and was sufficiently uncowered by the system act in such a way. It discounts the power of the state over Aboriginal people. The court stated:

I further find as a fact that the plaintiff’s mother at no time between 1942 and 1960 made application to the [Board] or, otherwise sought to have the plaintiff released from the [Board’s] control, or sought her restoration to her care within the meaning of ... the Act, nor was any discharge of the plaintiff sought at any time pursuant to ... the Act.

... [This] is consistent with a view that she did not wish the child’s status or relationship viz the Board to change ... nor did she wish to have the child returned to her care.[185]

In contrast, the Supreme Court of South Australia at trial accepted Bruce Trevorrow’s claim of false imprisonment on the basis that there was no parental or child consent. The Court held:

By being placed with [his foster mother], the plaintiff’s will was completely overborne. Given the plaintiff’s age at the time of the removal, he did not consent; neither did his parents. The plaintiff was imprisoned, and the State, through its agents and emanations, caused the imprisonment.[186]

The Trevorrow Cases challenge the operation of consent in practice—demonstrating that it was frequently quite meaningless, and that the documentary record concerning consent should not necessarily be trusted. However, the framework of liability still relies on consent, with its attendant problems regarding agency and good/bad parenting, in determining the success of the claim. Because of the nature of removal policies, as well as the legal categories under consideration, consent remains as one of the ‘stories that had normalized state intervention yet at the same time ignored the subjectivity and experience of Indigenous people altogether.[187] This means that claimants must still contend with this myth, and may have difficulty establishing claims where the documentary record does not demonstrate protests or the absence of consent on the part of their parents; or where the record demonstrates formal consent, despite significant evidence demonstrating problems with the meaningfulness of such formal consent. The presence of such myths is a key reason why the common law may continue to be a problematic site for the determination of responsibility for historical harms—one great advantage that a reparations scheme would provide would be a new framework, and a new language of responsibility, which take account of these tangled myths and histories, and law’s own complicity with these.

V. CONCLUSION: FUTURE DIRECTIONS IN STOLEN GENERATIONS LITIGATION
The Trevorrow Cases embody a new judicial reading of history and evidence in the Stolen Generations litigation. The extent to which this resulted in findings in favour of compensation is offset by Bruce Trevorrow’s experience, which made him in many ways an ‘ideal plaintiff’.[188] Although Julian Burnside, counsel for Bruce Trevorrow, emphasised that the outcome was not dependent upon the particular facts of the case, but is of relevance to future Stolen Generation litigation generally,[189] a significant factor contributing to the success of this particular case lay in Counsel’s ability to produce substantial evidence regarding Trevorrow’s removal. For many Indigenous claimants, as was notably the case in Cubillo and Williams, the establishment of documented evidence often presents a considerable challenge to the courts’ ability to determine critical findings of fact. Cockayne notes that Stolen Generations litigation ‘demand[s] the provision of evidence as to the consent and intentions of individuals in times now far removed, in cases where records are often scant’.[190]
Nonetheless, the contextual reading of the legal archive and understandings of general practice were key to the judiciary’s treatment of consent in the Trevorrow Cases. In previous cases, difficulties stemmed not only from such lapses in time since the occurrence of the tort, but also from the courts’ preference for written documentary evidence, which is ‘alien to the oral tradition in Aboriginal cultures’.[191] The Trevorrow Cases may signal a shift away from this onerous evidentiary burden and open the door for prospective successful litigation. The real test will be whether courts apply the Trevorrow Cases to cases where formal consent is present. Would a post-Lampard-Trevorrow Federal Court treat Topsy’s thumbprint as a product of state control, or would it once again take it on face value and denote Lampard-Trevorrow an exceptional status? Would a post-Lampard-Trevorrow NSW Supreme Court now recognise Joy Williams as a member of the Stolen Generations notwithstanding her mother’s consent noted in the documentary record?[192] If the effect of Lampard-Trevorrow in future cases is to disavow the operation of meaningful consent in the context of Stolen Generations removals, this would go a long way in providing meaningful legal outcomes for Indigenous plaintiffs. Under such an approach, the formal consent of Topsy’s thumbprint would be interpreted in the context of its historical production, and doubted as evidence of meaningful consent.
It is yet to be resolved whether the provision for a more contextualised understanding of the removal of children in the Trevorrow Cases is of significant precedential value or merely symbolic importance for potential Stolen Generation litigants. Either way, the Trevorrow Cases present opportunities for new judicial narratives on the Stolen Generations; ones that involve Aboriginal child policies being recognised as more than the sum of documentary evidence and thumbprints. Where judicial imaginings capture the ‘theft’ of Aboriginal children ‘from their culture, their history and their community’ at the hands of a colonising policy[193] the common law will be best positioned to adjudicate the historical suffering of the Stolen Generations. Such adjudication will provide closure for Stolen Generations litigants and an opening for the healing process.


[1] South Australia v Lampard-Trevorrow [2010] SASC 56; (2010) 106 SASR 331 (‘Lampard-Trevorrow’).
[2] Trevorrow v South Australia (No 5) [2007] SASC 285; (2007) 98 SASR 136 (‘Trevorrow’).
[3] The Full Court reversed the trial judge’s findings in two major respects: first, it found there was no false imprisonment in the circumstances (at [307]) and second, that no fiduciary duty was owed to Bruce Trevorrow (at [335]-[342]).
[4] Ann Genovese, ‘Metaphor of redemption, myths of state: Historical accountability in Luhrmann's Australia and Trevorrow v South Australia(2011) 20 Griffith Law Review 67;
Pam O’Connor, ‘History on Trial: Cubillo and Gunner v The Commonwealth of Australia[2001] AltLawJl 7; (2001) 26 Alternative Law Journal 27, 30. See also Chris Cuneen and Julia Grix, ‘The Limitations of Litigation in Stolen Generations Cases’ (Research Discussion Paper No 15, Australian Institute of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Studies, 2004); and Robert van Krieken ‘Is Assimilation Justiciable? Lorna Cubillo and Peter Gunner v Commonwealth’ [2001] SydLawRw 10; (2001) 23(2) Sydney Law Review 239.
[5] Genovese, above n 4, 74
[6] O’Connor, above n 4, 30. See also Cuneen and Grix, above n 4; van Krieken, above n 4.
[7] National Inquiry into the Separation of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Children from Their Families, Bringing them Home: Report of the National Inquiry into the Separation of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Children from Their Families (Sydney: Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission, 1997), 6, 8, 56. See also: Andrea Durbach, ‘Repairing the Damage: Achieving Reparations for the Stolen Generations’ (2002) 27 Alternative Law Journal 262.
[8] National Inquiry, above n 7, recommendation 3.
[9] Antonio Buti, ‘The Stolen Generations Litigation Revisited’ [2008] MelbULawRw 13; (2008) 32 Melbourne University Law Review 382, 383.
[10] Ibid, 420.
[11] Kruger v The Commonwealth [1997] HCA 27; (1997) 190 CLR 1 (‘Kruger’)
[12] Section 6 of the Ordinance gave power to the Chief Protector, (and under regulations made pursuant to section 67, all Protectors), to undertake the care, custody or control of Aboriginal people where it was in their best interests; section 7 made the Chief Protector the legal guardian of every Aboriginal person and every ‘half-cast’ child. Section 16 provided powers for the Chief Protector to remove any Aboriginal or ‘half-cast’ to an institution or Aboriginal reserve.
[13] Kruger, above n 11, 40 (Brennan CJ), 85-6 (Toohey J), 176 (Gummow J).
[14] Ibid, 41 (Brennan CJ), 53 (Dawson J), 79 (Toohey J), 104 (Gaudron J), 141 (McHugh J), 161 (Gummow J).
[15] Ibid 45 (Brennan CJ), 70 (Dawson J), 142 (McHugh J), 157 (Gummow J).
[16] Ibid 44-5 (Brennan CJ), 68 (Dawson J), 114 (Gaudron J), 155 (Gummow J).
[17] Ibid 70-1 (Dawson J), 88 (Toohey J), 107 (Gaudron J), 144 (McHugh J), 158-189 (Gummow J).
[18] Kruger, above n 11, 44-5 (Brennan CJ), 63-8 (Dawson J), 142 (McHugh J), 153-9 (Gummow J).
[19] Ibid 46 (Brennan CJ), 93 (Toohey J), 125-126 (Gaudron J).
[20] Gaudron J at 107 found it possible that the grant of legislative power in s 122 of the Constitution does not ‘authorise gross violations of human rights and dignity contrary to the established principles of the common law.’
[21] Kruger, above n 11, 36 (Brennan CJ).
[22] Ibid 36-7 (Brennan CJ) and 52 (Dawson J).
[23] Cubillo v The Commonwealth [No 2] [2001] FCA 887; (2000) 112 FCR 1 (‘Cubillo Trial’). A number of aspects favourable to the applicants were reversed on appeal, but all adverse findings were affirmed: Cubillo v The Commonwealth [2001] FCA 1213; (2001) 112 FCR 455 (‘Cubillo Appeal’).
[24] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 2.
[25] Cubillo v Commonwealth [1999] FCA 518; (1999) 89 FCR 528 (‘strike out application’) [1999] FCA 518; (1999) 89 FCR 528, 599 (O’Loughlin J).
[26] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 483 (O’Loughlin J).
[27] Ibid, 103-8; 358.
[28] Ibid, 483.
[29] Ibid, 148, 150.
[30] Transcript of Proceedings, Cubillo v Commonwealth (High Court of Australia, Gleeson CJ, 3 May 2002).
[31] Williams v The Minister, Aboriginal Land Rights Act 1983 and Anor [1999] NSWSC 843 (Williams Trial). This finding was upheld on appeal: Williams v The Minister Aboriginal Land Rights Act 1983 and New South Wales [2000] NSWCA 255 (Williams Appeal).
[32] Williams Trial, above n 31, [32].
[33] Ibid, [160].
[34] Trevorrow, above n 2, 393.
[35] Ibid.
[36] Ibid, 216-50.
[37] Ibid, 239.
[38] Genovese, above n 4, 82.
[39] Trevorrow, above n 2, 239.
[40] Ibid, 244.
[41] Ibid, 248.
[42] Buti above n 9, 413.
[43] Ibid.
[44] Cubillo Appeal, above n 23, 529.
[45] For example: Paul Finn and Kathryn Smith, ‘The Citizen, The Government and ‘Reasonable Expectations’’ (1992) 66 Australian Law Journal 139, 145; van Krieken, above n 4.
[46] Buti, above n 9, 397.
[47] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [275].
[48] Trevorrow, above n 2, 216-239, 335-373. See also Buti, above n 9, 415.
[49] See Buti, above n 9, 406.
[50] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 147-8 (O’Loughlin J); Williams (time extension appeal) (1994) 35 NSWLR 497, 506-7 (Kirby P). See also: Cunneen and Grix, above n 4, 27.
[51] Buti, above n 9, 416.
[52] Ibid, 400.
[53] (1994-1995) 185 CLR 307, 347.
[54] (1998) 196 CLR 329, 344.
[55] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [263].
[56] Ibid, [265].
[57] Trevorrow, above n 2, 338-339.
[58] Ibid, 340-343.
[59] (1919) 122 LT 44, 53 (Atkin LJ)
[60] [1988] UKHL 13.
[61] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [290], [292].
[62] Ibid, [285].
[63] Ibid, [284].
[64] Ibid, [285].
[65] Ibid, [298].
[66] Williams Trial, above n 31, 293.
[67] [2007] SASC 285; (2007) 98 SASR 136, [1006].
[68] Ibid, [337].
[69] Ibid, [333].
[70] Ibid, [337].
[71] (1995-1996) 186 CLR 71, 82.
[72] Ibid, [337].
[73] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [337].
[74] Ibid, [335].
[75] Ibid, [332].
[76] Ibid, [343].
[77] Ibid, [363].
[78] Williams Appeal, above n 31, [160]-[162].
[79] Buti, above n 9, 406.
[80] Trevorrow [2007] SASC 285; (2007) 98 SASR 136, 366.
[81] [1999] HCA 59; (1999) 200 CLR 1, [114].
[82] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [367].
[83] Aborigines Act 1934 (SA) s 10.
[84] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [370].
[85] Ibid, [406].
[86] Ibid, [412].
[87] Ibid, [413].
Cubillo Trial, above n 23, [1421]. See also, Cubillo Appeal, above n 23, [295].
[88] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, [439].
[89] John Rush, ‘Cubillo and Gunner revisited: A Question of National Character’ (2008) 12 Australian Indigenous Law Review 25, 29.
[90] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, [1400].
[91] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [463].
[92] [1987] HCA 57; (1987) 163 CLR 628, 635, quoted in Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [426].
[93] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [442].
[94] Ibid, [460].
[95] Ibid, [462].
[96] Ibid, [227].
[97] [1985] HCA 81; (1985) 159 CLR 550, 584, quoted in Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [227].
[98] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [230].
[99] [1990] HCA 57; (1990) 170 CLR 596; (1986-1987) 162 CLR 447.
[100] Lampard-Trevorrow (2010) 106 SASR 33, [238].
[101] [1987] HCA 4; (1986-1987) 162 CLR 447, 458, quoted in Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [233].
[102] Ann Curthoys, Ann Genovese and Alexander Reilly, Rights and Redemption: History, Law and Indigenous People (Sydney: UNSW Press, 2008), 223–4.
[103] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 483.
[104] Ibid, 357.
[105] van Krieken, above n 4, 246.
[106] Ibid, 245-6.
[107] Ibid, 246.
[108] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 344.

[109] Ibid.

[110] Ibid, 262.
[111] Ibid, 263.
[112] Ibid, 251.
[113] Ibid, 265.
[114] Ibid, 251, emphasis ours.
[115] Ibid, 179.
[116] Ibid, 265.
[117] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1; Trevorrow, above n 2.
[118] Trish Luker, ‘Intention and Iterability in Cubillo v Commonwealth’ (2005) 84(1) Journal of Australian Studies 84 35.
[119] Cunneen and Grix, above n 4, 14.
[120] Buti, above n 9, 416.
[121] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [47].
[122] Ibid, [88].
[123] Ibid, [84]. Here, as in excerpts discussed below, the court was relying on findings of fact at first instance.
[124] Ibid, [126].
[125] Ibid, [126].
[126] Ibid, [127].
[127] Ibid, [128].
[128] Ibid.
[129] Ibid.
[130] Ibid, [126].
[131] Ibid, [133].
[132] Ibid, [132].
[133] Ibid, [133].
[134] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 179.
[135] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [133].
[136] See Cuneen and Grix, above n 4, 5.
[137] Genovese, above n 4, 71.
[138] Ibid, 72.
[139] Curthoys et al, above n 103.
[140] Genovese, above n 4, 72.
[141] van Krieken, above n 4, 239.
[142] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 70.
[143] See Curthoys et al, above n 103, 134-166.
[144] Cubillo Trial, above n 23, 482.
[145] Ibid, 483.
[146] Ibid, above n 23, 96-98, quoting Brennan CJ in Kruger, above n 11, 36-7 and Dawson J at 52.
[147] Trevorrow, above n 2, 239, referring to the judicial recognition in Kruger, above n 11, 40.
[148] Trevorrow, above n 2, 390, citing Harris v Digital Pulse Pty Ltd [2003] NSWCA 10; (2003) 56 NSWLR 298 at 113.
[149] Trevorrow, above n 2, 393.
[150] Genovese, above n 4, 83.
[151] Ibid, 85.
[152] Ibid.
[153] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [461].
[154] Williams Trial, above n 31. Williams Appeal, above n 31.
[155] Cubillo Trial, above n 23.
[156] Trevorrow above n 2; Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1.
[157] Cubillo Appeal, above n 23, 262, 263.
[158] Ibid, 352.
[159] Aborigines Act 1934 (SA) s 10.
[160] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [196].
[161] (2003) 211 CLR 476, [30].
[162] Lampard-Trevorrow, above n 1, [196].
[163] Ibid, [222].
[164] Ibid, [223].
[165] See, for example, Cubillo Trial, above n 23.
[166] Williams Trial, above n 31. Williams Appeal, above n 31.
[167] The Supreme Court relied on s 7(2) of the Aborigines Protection Act 1909 provided: ‘The board may on the application of the parent or guardian of any child admit such child to the control of the board’: Williams Trial, above n 31, [26].
[168] Williams Trial, above n 31, [142]. The Court stated, ‘My finding is that the AWB considered the mother's application to give up control of the plaintiff to its control, and having done so, admitted the child to its control. I find that there was not any removal by the Board to the plaintiff, in the sense of taking the child against the will of the mother. The plaintiff was taken into the AWB’s control because the mother did not want the child, could not keep the child and asked the AWB to take control of her: see s 7(2)’: Williams Trial, above n 31, [26].
[169] Williams Appeal, above n 31, [58].
[170] National Inquiry, above n 7, 86, quoting ‘Confidential evidence 384, Tasmania’.
[171] National Inquiry, above n 7, 41.
[172] Ibid, 40.
[173] Ibid, 51.
[174] Ibid, 56.
[175] Ibid, 7–8.
[176] Sadiya V. Hartman, Scenes of Subjection: Terror, Slavery, and Self-Making In Nineteenth-Century America (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), 85.
[177] Ibid, 40.
[178] ‘Whiteness’ is a cultural historical construct (Ghassan Hage, White Nation: Fantasies of White Supremacy in a Multicultural Society (Sydney: Pluto Press 1998), 58–9), which involves ‘both a European monopolisation of ‘civilised humanity’ and a parallel monopolisation of Whiteness as its marker’ (Ghassan Hage, Against Paranoid Nationalism: Searching for Hope in a Shrinking Society (Sydney: Pluto Press, 2003), 49–50).
[179] Hartman, above n 177, 89.
[180] National Inquiry, above n 7, 6, 8, 56.
[181] Hartman, above n 177, 88.
[182] Ibid.
[183] Quoted in Annie White, ‘Joy Williams loses her Stolen Generations Case’, The World Today: ABC Local Radio, 26 August 1999, accessed on 30 April 2012, http://www.abc.net.au/worldtoday/stories/s46829.htm.
[184] Cuneen and Grix, above n 4, 24.
[185] Williams Trial, above n 31, [179].
[186] Trevorrow, above n 2, 982.
[187] Genovese, above n 4, 74.
[188] Buti, above n 9, 420.
[189] Julian Burnside, ‘Stolen Generation: Time for a Change’ (2007) 32 Alternative Law Journal 131, 132.
[190] James Cockayne, ‘More Than Sorry: Constructing a Legal Architecture for Practical Reconciliation’ [2001] SydLawRw 23; (2001) 23 Sydney Law Review 577, 581. Also see: Buti, above n 11, 415.
[191] Chris Cunneen and Julia Grix, above n 4, 27.
[192] The refusal of such recognition was noted in: Williams Trial, note 31, [5].
[193] van Krieken, above n 4, 240.


AustLII: Copyright Policy | Disclaimers | Privacy Policy | Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UTSLRS/2012/21.html